Tuesday, September 7, 2010

A Response to Tim Crane's Article in the NYT on Science and Religion

In today’s New York Times, Tim Crane has written a piece entitled “Mystery and Evidence” (click here to read the article) on the relationship between science and religion, ostensibly with the purpose of promoting understanding between believers and non-believers. It should be mentioned that Crane describes himself as an atheist in the article, and is writing as one who is sympathetic to religion, even as he rejects it (something he goes so far as to disclose in the article).

I am truly appalled by the lack of intellectual rigour and the unsophisticated thinking that Crane displays in his article—especially since he professes to espouse atheism. One would expect something of a higher calibre from an atheist. Perhaps he is “stooping to conquer”—stooping, that is, to the level of the believer—but at what price? Whatever the case may be, he displays at best a tenuous grasp of both science and religion and is certainly not qualified to write on either subject. Anyone who can write a statement such as “Science too has its share of mysteries (or rather: things that must simply be accepted without further explanation)” is immediately disqualified from writing anything worthwhile about science—and, by extension, about its relation to religion.

With regard to science, the picture that he paints of what it is all about is at best a grotesque caricature. He writes: “The essence of science involves making hypotheses about the causes and natures of things ….” This is a very narrow view of what scientists do. Science is both inductive and deductive, and hypothesis-formulation is only one (perhaps rather small) aspect of what is involved. By harping on the “hypothesis” idea (the word “hypothesis” in its various forms appears at least 20 times in the article by my count), and using that as the pivot upon which he turns the difference between science and religion, he obfuscates the issue and does a disservice to both science and religion. In its broadest sense, science is the activity of investigating natural and social phenomena and factual claims about them. It is true that in the so-called “scientific method,” hypotheses are proposed and tested, but this is a very small part of what scientists actually do.

When, for example, the police claim that a crime has been committed, the forensic scientist is called in to investigate this claim with the intention of determining whether the claim is true or false, and no hypothesis is involved whatsoever. The police may have some “hypothesis” about who committed the crime (what they call “the suspect”), but the forensic scientist has no interest at all in this hypothesis. Forensic science merely examines the evidence left at the scene of the alleged crime and interprets it for the police. If forensics is being applied to a dead body, for example, it can say with a fair degree of certainty whether the death was intentional or accidental. If the latter is the case, science can say definitively that the claim that a crime was committed is false. This is the deductive aspect of science, and it is observed widely throughout all the scientific disciplines. Actuarial science, for example, applies (deductively) the principles of statistical mathematics to the assessment of risk, without any need of hypotheses. Materials science is in the business of applying already existing scientific knowledge to explaining why certain materials behave in the way that they do and to the production of new and better materials—and hypotheses (in the strict sense of the term) simply do not enter into the picture. There are dozens of other scientific disciplines like these three in which hypothesizing is simply not involved in any fundamental way. In this broad understanding of science—that is, science as the investigation of phenomena and factual claims—history, too, is a “science” in that it proceeds by examining what evidence there is for claims that a certain event occurred. No historian worthy of the name would write a history of the Second World War, for example, without looking into the evidence that might exist for the systematic extermination of the Jews in Nazi Germany. So-called “Holocaust deniers” claim that the evidence is insufficient or non-existent, but most historians are convinced, on the basis of the evidence that does exist, that the “Holocaust” did occur. They are convinced, not merely because the Jews claim that they were persecuted by the Nazi, but because these historians have examined the evidence scientifically in an attempt to verify or disconfirm the claim. They use scientific methods and principles to authenticate documents and other artefacts, but do not typically employ hypotheses in what they do.

Crane mentions history and the historical claims made by religions, and in particular he refers to the centrality of the historical claims made by Christianity. But once again, he clouds the issue by couching the discussion in the language of “hypotheses” and conflating “claims” and “hypotheses.” He seems to be unaware of the fundamental difference between the two. A claim is a statement that something is true without accompanying evidence to back it up. An hypothesis is a tentative explanation for some observed phenomenon. History is not interested in hypotheses, since it is not in the business of offering explanations, tentative or otherwise. In the process of writing a reliable account of the past, historians investigate claims that certain events occurred, looking for evidence that might substantiate or nullify the claim. In this sense, history is as much a science as physics or chemistry or forensics, and it works in collaboration with other sciences, such as archaeology, chemistry, botany, and many more. Two good examples of how history works “scientifically” in collaboration with other sciences involve the controversies surrounding the Shroud of Turin and the James Ossuary, both of which have a bearing on the historical claims of Christianity. The general consensus of science and history is that both artefacts are forgeries and that the "religious" claims surrounding them are therefore false.

The mention of the Shroud of Turin and the James Ossuary brings us to an examination of Crane’s claims about evidence and its place in religion. He suggests that evidence is irrelevant or at least inconsequential to religious belief. However, the very presence of the Shroud of Turin, the James Ossuary, and a multitude of other religious artefacts and relics bears silent witness to the importance of evidence for Christian belief. Evidence is, in fact, so important to the believer that it needs to be fabricated when none exists, as in the two examples just mentioned. There would be no need for the Shroud of Turin and the James Ossuary if evidence was not important to the believer. The only reason that these objects exists is that somebody somewhere was eager to establish the historicity of Christ.

One of the fundamental goals of the believer, at least in Christianity and Islam, is to convert the non-believer, and the best way to do this, apparently, is to offer evidence (fabricated or otherwise). The pagans of pre-Christian Europe were loath to relinquish their paganism, and it was only through “signs and wonders” (and occasionally a combination of trickery and coercion) that the Church was able to convince them to forsake their pagan ways and adopt Christianity. In our own time, the Intelligent Design movement is another attempt on the part of believers to convince non-believers of the validity of Creationism through so-called “scientific” evidence. What is more, the Bible is replete with examples of evidence-proffering. The Ten Plagues on Egypt were supposedly Moses’ way of offering Pharaoh evidence that Yahweh was more powerful than the Egyptian gods. The “Empty Tomb” is continually held up as evidence of Christ’s resurrection. Christ himself invoked the “evidence principle” in his now oft-repeated dictum: “By their fruits ye shall know them” (Matt. 7: 16). And he wasn’t above offering “Doubting Thomas” physical evidence of his corporeality, while at the same time tut-tutting at that unfortunate apostle’s skepticism and lack of faith and his demand for empirical evidence. What is more, Christ rather shamelessly made a public display of performing spectacular miracles as evidence of his divinity—or at least of his special access to his Father in heaven. And he conferred on his disciples the power to perform similar miracles as well—and seventy of them went out and did precisely what he empowered them to do as part of their preaching and proselytizing. If Christ had been really concerned about healing the sick and helping people, he could have (and would have) done so quietly, in private, without any ostentatious display (something he hypocritically accused the Pharisees of). But most of his miracles (at least as they are recorded in the gospels) were performed in very public places in the presence of large crowds of people—the very first one being performed at a wedding, no less, and it certainly “wowed” the crowd. It is a sobering thought that before there was Madison Avenue, Christ (as he is portrayed in the gospels) had mastered the art of self-promotion and publicity through spectacular displays of “evidence.”

Christians are always looking for evidence to justify and confirm their faith, and every little coincidence is seized upon as evidence of the existence of God and of his love and care for those who believe in him. Crane mentions prayers that go unanswered as evidence that Christians are not concerned with evidence, but one has simply to look through the vast body of Christian literature to find millions of examples of claims of prayers being answered. What is this if it is not evidence gathering? Why bother mentioning that one’s prayers were answered if evidence is not important? The problem with Christianity is not that it dismisses evidence altogether, but rather that it reserves the right to pick and choose what evidence it will consider and what it will disregard and suppress. This is one of the things that sets it apart from science. The scientist does not allow himself or herself the luxury of choosing his or her evidence, and in this the scientist can be said to have much greater integrity than the religionist. Scientists are bound by the code of conduct of their profession to go wherever the evidence leads; religionists do not set such limits upon themselves. For them evidence is a matter of convenience: they will capitalize on it when it is convenient for them to do so and when it promotes their cause.

To return to the place of historical claims in religion, Crane writes: “Christianity does make factual, historical claims. But this is not the same as being a kind of proto-science.” However, as I have just shown, any historical claim, no matter who makes it, is subject to verification by scientific methods. He further goes on to make the remarkably ignorant statement that “[r]eligions do make factual and historical claims, and if these claims are false, then the religions fail.” I do not know which planet Crane is living on, but on this planet no religion has ever failed because its historical claims have been demonstrated to be false. Christianity has survived for nearly 2000 years despite the fact that many of its historical claims have been shown to be untrue, or at least not possible within the known laws of the physical universe—most notably the claims of the Resurrection and Ascension of Christ. Judaism has survived even longer in the face of patently false claims such as the one that God promised the Land of Israel to the descendants of Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob—and Judaism has survived notwithstanding (and perhaps even because of) all the blood that has been shed in pursuit of this claim. Both Christianity and Judaism suffer from the lack of historicity of much of the so-called “historical” material in the Old Testament. “Secular” historians and archaeologists can find no evidence whatsoever outside the Old Testament for the existence of a King David, the fall of Jericho, the drowning of Pharaoh’s army in the Red Sea, and a host of other historical claims found in the Old Testament. In fact, they have found evidence that many of these events could not have happened as they are described in the Old Testament. As with evidence, history is a matter of convenience to the believer. History is invoked whenever it is convenient to do so (as is the case with Jewish claims regarding Jewish "ownership" of the land of Palestine).

There is much else that is wrong with Crane’s article, and it is impossible to disentangle all his various errors from his few statements of truth in this response (several readers of the article commented on some of these in the NYT). However, if Crane really wants to talk about the differences between science and religion, he should be talking about the following:

(1) Each religion claims that it is the sole repository of the truth and that all other religions are false. Science knows no such “jingoism.” There are no “brands” of science each vying for supremacy. The various disciplines of science cooperate with each other and do not see other disciplines as rivals. The physicist’s view of the world is not pitted against the chemist’s or the biologist’s. They complement each other. But where would you find a religionist who would admit that Islam complements Christianity or Buddhism complements Judaism?

(2) Religions are, typically, intolerant of other religions and seek to suppress them through aggressive means. Just consider the number of wars that have been fought in the name of religion, and the amount of human blood that has been spilled. No war that I am aware of has ever been fought over a scientific principle or theory.

(3) Religions do not allow internal dissent and freedom of expression. Anyone who challenges the orthodox position (that is, “toe the party line”) is immediately branded a heretic and burned at the stake or otherwise “neutralized.” This is not just confined to the Middle Ages. In our own time, the Catholic Church silenced (with a heavy hand) the voice of Liberation Theology, a movement that arose within the Church in Latin America, largely through the overzealous efforts of then Cardinal Joseph Ratzinger (now Pope Benedict XVI). In sharp contrast, science welcomes dissent, for it is in dissent that we arrive at a closer approximation to the truth about the world around us. A prime example is Einstein’s successful challenge of Newtonian orthodoxy and Darwin’s challenge of the notion of the fixity of species. Another more recent example is what has come to be known, somewhat facetiously, as the “Black Hole War.” In 1983, Stephen Hawking argued (convincingly) that black holes evaporate and that the information they contain evaporates along with them and is thus lost forever. Coming from one so eminent in scientific circles as Hawking, this view might have been considered “scientific orthodoxy.” However, over the next few years, Leonard Susskind offered a dissenting view and was able to prove (more convincingly) that Hawking was mistaken. Hawking very graciously admitted that he was wrong and the business of science went on without further ado, incorporating Susskind’s new insights. Such collegiality is unimaginable among religions. As recently as 2007, Benedict XVI issued a statement that the Catholic Church considers itself the only true Church (and, by extension, that Catholicism is the only true religion). Do we need to mention his remarks about Islam, which offended millions of Muslims all over the world? Do we need to mention how reluctant he was to admit the Church’s culpability in handling sexually abusive priests? Benedict XVI would not survive for a day as an ordinary scientist, let alone as the head of a major scientific institution, yet he seems to be doing quite well in his current position as head of the world's largest Christian denomination.

(4) As already mentioned above, religion is not particularly concerned with intellectual honesty. It is the prime example of “selective attention,” picking and choosing whatever is in its best interests, and suppressing anything that poses a threat to these interests, through bans and prohibitions and taboos. Science has no vested interest in any particular scientific theory or idea, and scientific bans and prohibitions are unheard of (at least in contemporary science). Science embraces all evidence, especially evidence that runs counter to existing theories and generally accepted explanations. For scientists, this contrary evidence is the most exciting aspect of the scientific endeavour, for it leads to new breakthroughs and a new understanding of the world.

These are but a few of the genuinely important differences between science and religion. The ones that Crane mentions in his article are mere pablum—not worthy of intellectually rigorous discourse. As I see it, Crane’s article is symptomatic of the currently fashionable practice of valuing everything and not being “judgmental.” This approach does nothing to further the cause of understanding the way believers think: it succeeds only in scrounging up the lamest excuses for their closed-mindedness and lack of intellectual honesty. I don’t think atheists suffer from a lack of understanding of believers. After all, most atheists in the West were brought up within the Judaeo-Christian tradition and are only too familiar with the way believers think. They once thought in exactly the same way themselves, but were somehow able to bootstrap themselves out of the mire of religious belief. The only way to engage believers (if we want to engage them at all) is to show them that we do not buy into the delusions that they have allowed themselves to be taken in by. I speak here of the West rather than of Third World countries, where there is really no way out of the mire in the absence of education, freedom of speech, or easy access to the body of knowledge that humans have accumulated so far.

In its namby-pamby, softly-softly, let’s-be-understanding approach, Crane’s article is a prime example of the art of calling a spade “a certain garden implement.” Where would be world be today if reformers such as Martin Luther had adopted Crane’s attitude? Luther certainly knew how to call a spade a spade, and he changed the course of Western history precisely because he did not balk at doing so. We need more people like him today and less of the Crane variety.